Keyboard Shortcuts?f

×
  • Next step
  • Previous step
  • Skip this slide
  • Previous slide
  • mShow slide thumbnails
  • nShow notes
  • hShow handout latex source
  • NShow talk notes latex source

Click here and press the right key for the next slide.

(This may not work on mobile or ipad. You can try using chrome or firefox, but even that may fail. Sorry.)

also ...

Press the left key to go backwards (or swipe right)

Press n to toggle whether notes are shown (or add '?notes' to the url before the #)

Press m or double tap to slide thumbnails (menu)

Press ? at any time to show the keyboard shortcuts

 

Dual Process Theories: Objections, Evidence and Significance

 

Lecture 08

Moral Psychology

While lots of lectures are self-standing, today’s lecture builds on lecture 07. And in particular on the loose reconstruction of Greene’s argument.

continues Lecture 07

Could scientific discoveries undermine, or support,
ethical principles?

Phase 2

Identify general arguments against the use of intuitions in doing ethics.

Consider implications for Rawl’s method of
reflective equilibrium.

Phase 1

Find places where a particular philosopher’s ethical argument relies on an empirical claim, and where knowledge of this claim depends on scientific discoveries.

Can be supportive rather than debunking. However, practically speaking, it’s easier to show that knowledge of the claim depends on scientific discoveries when the science contradicts the ethicist’s claim. (Otherwise it’s hard to show that the ethicist knew the claim was true all along.)

The essence of anti-intuition arguments is captured by Railton (who is offering considerations with which to counter them):

‘a better understanding of the [...] origin of “intuitive” moral judgments might show them to be something other than manifestations of underlying moral competencies or principles.

moral intuitions” might therefore deserve less deference [...] than they characteristically receive in philosophical [...] moral thought’

(Railton, 2014, p. 832).

As Railton makes clear, there are several ways of developing this idea. We have been pursuing one such way.

So?

One response to our argument has been to deny that philosophers ever rely on intuitions (Cappelen, 2012). But that is not a widely held view (and we can give deeper objections, but let’s not get side-tracked).

Intuition is a resource in all of philosophy, but perhaps nowhere more than in ethics’

(Audi, 2015, p. 57).

‘Episodic intuitions [...] can serve as data [...] ... beliefs that derive from them receive prima facie justification’ (p. 65).

Always gotta ask what it means. Audi explains it in terms of self-evidence (if you understand it you know it).

‘self-evident propositions are truths meeting two conditions: (1) in virtue of adequately understanding them, one has justification for believing them [...]; and (2) believing them on the basis of adequately understanding them entails knowing them’ (p. 65).

We understand why someone might think there were such things. But how could such things exist in the domain of ethics?
The only possibility I’m aware of is that they are a consequence of fast processes.
In familiar situations and concerning matters that are significant for reproductive success, fast process are super reliable. So if there are judgements the give rise to, it’s just conceivable that the corresponding propositions could be self-evidence in Audi’s sense.
Or maybe there just are not self-evident propositions in ethics.

previously

Not-justified-inferentially premises about particular moral scenarios cannot be used in ethical arguments where the aim is knowledge.

plan for today

Evidence for the dual-process theory

Evidence against the dual-process theory

Significance (phase I: reflective equilibrium)